CUBICAL
Cubical implements an experimental simple type-checker for type theory
with univalence with an evaluator for closed terms.
INSTALL
To install cubical a working Haskell and cabal installation are
required. To build cubical go to the main directory and do
cabal install
To only build (not install) cubical do
cabal configure
cabal build
Alternatively one can also use the Makefile to build the system by typing:
make bnfc && make
However this requires that the following Haskell packages are installed:
mtl, haskeline, directory, BNFC, alex, happy
USAGE
To run cubical type
cubical <filename>
In the interaction loop type :h to get a list of available commands.
Note that the current directory will be taken as the search path for
the imports.
OVERVIEW
The program is organized as follows:
-
the files are parsed and produce a list of definitions; the syntax
is described in the file Exp/Doc.txt or Exp/Doc.tex (auto generated
by bnfc);
-
this list of definitions is type-checked;
-
if successful, we can then write an expression which is
type-checked w.r.t. these definitions;
-
if the expression is well-typed it is translated to the cubical
syntax and evaluated by a "cubical abstract machine", which
computes its semantics in cubical sets; the result is shown after
"EVAL:" (to disable the trace of the evaluation set the boolean
"debug" to False in Eval.hs);
During type-checking, we consider the primitives listed in
examples/primitive.cub as non interpreted constants. The type-checker
is in the file MTT.hs and is rudimentary (300 lines), without good
error messages.
These primitives however have a meaning in cubical sets, and the
evaluation function computes this meaning. This semantics/evaluation
is described in the file Eval.hs, which is the main file. The most
complex part corresponds to the computations witnessing that the
universe has Kan filling operations.
For writing this semantics, it was convenient to use the alternative
presentation of cubical sets as nominal sets with 01-substitutions
(see A. Pitts' note, references listed below).
DESCRIPTION OF THE LANGUAGE
We have
-
dependent function types (x:A) -> B
; non-dependent function types
can be written as A -> B
-
abstraction \x -> e
-
named/labelled sum c1 (x1:A1)...(xn:An) | c2 ... | ...
a data type is a recursively defined named sum
-
function defined by case
f = split c1 x1 ... xn -> e1 | c2 ... -> ... | ...
-
a universe U
and assume U:U
for simplicity
-
let/where: let D in e
where D is a list of definitions an
alternative syntax is e where D
-
undefined
like in Haskell
The syntax allows Landin's offside rule similar to Haskell.
The basic (untyped) language has a direct simple denotational
semantics. Type theory works with the total part of this language (it
is possible to define totality at the denotational semantics level).
Our evaluator works in a nominal version of this semantics. The
type-checker assumes that we work in this total part, however,
there is no termination check.
DESCRIPTION OF THE SEMANTICS/EVALUATION
The values depend on a new class of names, also called directions,
which can be thought of as varying over the unit interval [0,1]. A
path connecting a0 and a1 in the direction x is a value p(x) such that
p(0) = a0 and p(1) = a1. An element in the identity type a0 = a1 is
then of the form <x>p(x) where the name x is bound. An identity proof
in an identity type will then be interpreted as a "square" of the form
<x><y>p(x,y). See examples/hedberg.cub and the example test3 (in the
current implementation directions/names are represented by numbers).
Operationally, a type is explained by giving what are its Kan filling
operation. For instance, we have to explain what are the Kan filling
for the dependent product.
The main step for interpreting univalence is to transform an
equivalence A -> B to a path in any direction x connecting A and B.
This is a new basic element of the universe, called VEquivEq in the
file Eval.hs which takes a name and arguments A,B,f and the proof that
f is an equivalence. The main part of the work is then to explain the
Kan filling operation for this new type.
The Kan filling for the universe can be seen as a generalization of
the operation of composition of relation.
DESCRIPTION OF THE EXAMPLES
The directory examples contains some examples of proofs. The file
examples/primitive.cub list the new primitives that have cubical set
semantics. These primitive notions imply the axiom of univalence. The
file examples/primitive.cub should be the basis of any development
using univalence.
Most of the example files contain simple test examples of
computations:
-
the file hedberg.cub contains a test computation of a square in
Nat; the example is test. In the type Nat or Bool, any square
(proof of identity of two identity proofs) is constant.
-
The file nIso.cub contains a non trivial example of a transport of
a section of a dependent type along the isomorphism between N and
N+1; the examples are testSN, testSN1, testSN2, testSN3.
-
The file testInh.cub contains examples of computation for the
propositional reflection. It gives an example test which produces
a (surprisingly complex) composition of squares in the universe.
-
The file quotient.cub contains an example of a computation from an
equivalence class. The relation R over Nat is to have the same
parity, and the map is Nat/R -> Bool which returns true if the
equivalence class contains even number. The examples are test5 and
test8 which computes the value of this map on the equivalence class
of five and eight respectively. This uses the file description.cub
which justifies the axiom of description.
-
The file Kraus.cub contains the example of Nicolai Kraus of the
myst function, which also shows that we can extract computational
information from propositions; the example is testMyst zero; the
computation does not create higher dimensional objects.
-
The file swap.cub contains examples of transport along the
isomorphism between A x B and B x A; the examples are test14,
test15.
FURTHER WORK (non-exhaustive)
-
The Kan filling operations should be formally proved correct and
tested on higher inductive types.
-
Some constants have a direct cubical semantics having better
behavior w.r.t. equality. For instance the constant
cong : (A B : U) (f : A -> B) (a b : A) (p : Id A a b) -> Id B (f a) (f b)
has a semantics which satisfies the definitional equalities:
cong (id A) = id A
cong (g o f) = (cong g) o (cong f)
cong f (refl A a) = refl B (f a)
The evaluation should be used for conversion during type-checking,
and then we shall get these equalities as definitional.
Some proofs are then much simpler, e.g. the proof of the Graduate
Lemma.
-
Similarly we should have eta conversion and surjective pairing;
this can be obtained by normalization by evaluation.
-
For higher inductive types, like the circle or the sphere, it would
be appropriate to extend the syntax of type theory, in order to
get natural elimination rules (see the paper on cubical sets).
-
To explore the termination of the resizing rule. Computationally
the resizing rule does not do anything, but the termination seems
to be an interesting proof-theoretical problem.
REFERENCES
-
Voevodsky's home page on univalent foundation
-
HoTT book
-
Type Theory in Color, J.P. Bernardy, G. Moulin
-
A simple type-theoretic language: Mini-TT, Th. Coquand,
Y. Kinoshita, B. Nordstrom and M. Takeyama
-
A cubical set model of type theory, M. Bezem, Th. Coquand and
S. Huber available at www.cse.chalmers.se/~coquand/model1.pdf
-
A property of contractible types, Th. Coquand available at
www.cse.chalmers.se/~coquand/contr.pdf
-
An equivalent presentation of the Bezem-Coquand-Huber category of
cubical sets, A. Pitts
AUTHORS
Cyril Cohen, Thierry Coquand, Simon Huber, Anders M�rtberg